Thursday, December 4, 2008
Brave New World of propaganda
Tuesday, December 2, 2008
V for Vendetta, Part 1
Wednesday, November 19, 2008
The unified state and the common enemy
Wednesday, November 12, 2008
The days of old are new again
Wednesday, November 5, 2008
The Anarchist's Fakebook?
Monday, October 27, 2008
Thought about it, but totally didn't get it
Sunday, October 19, 2008
Equality in diversity
Sunday, October 12, 2008
You can't take it with you
Thursday, October 9, 2008
To the BBC, because it successfully predicts my life
Sunday, October 5, 2008
Things that are bad ideas
Thursday, October 2, 2008
So many buzzwords, so little time
Sunday, September 28, 2008
For richer or for poorer
Thursday, September 25, 2008
INVISIBLE HAND OF DOOM
Thursday, September 18, 2008
Hooray for Hypocrisy!
This week we read a speech delivered by Frederick Douglass at the celebration of the 76th anniversary of the Fourth of July. Douglass, unusually for his time, was greatly respected and honored former slave. As demonstrated in "What to the Slave is the Fourth of July?," Douglass was a strong believer in liberalism and in the liberal and democratic principles the United States was founded on.
Douglass expresses his beliefs as clearly as possible in the text of his speech. He repeatedly attests to a love and respect for the founders of the nation, saying "they loved their country better than their own private interests; and, though this not the highest form of human excellence, all will concede that it is a rare virtue, and that when it is exhibited, it ought to command respect."
In spite of - or perhaps because of - this love, Douglass insists on sharing wit the audience the hypocrisy of their celebration. While they enjoy the freedoms and luxuries bequeathed by their forefathers, American citizens were displaying the same tyranny toward slaves that England displayed toward Americans: "You boast of your love of liberty, your superior civilization, and your pure Christianity, while the whole political power of the nation [...] is solemnly pledged to support and perpetuate the enslavement of three millions of your country men."
Douglass uses the sparks of the Revolution as a parallel to the cruelty of slavery. Douglass refreshes the memory of an imperialist ruler that handed down rulings and laws found to be oppressive and unreasonable. Douglass describes the actions of the patriots in terms that would be equally adequate for abolitionists: "to pronounce against England, and in favor of the cause of the colonies, tried men's souls. They who did so were accounted in their day, plotters of mischief, agitators and rebels, dangerous men." Douglass further notes that actions American citizens respected in their fathers were reviled in their contemporaries.
When the patriots felt that England gone too far, done too much wrong against their brethren, they chose to rebel and declare their independence. They were ultimately successful, creating a new nation of freedom and hope, a nation where the government was accountable to the people. As Douglass states, these "blessings, in which you, this day, rejoice, are not enjoyed in common." The American people turned their back on the principles of the Declaration, turned a blind eye to the suffering of others.
Douglass is realistic, but ultimately hopeful for the future of the nation. He believed that the nation's youth kept it from being too set in its ways, and eventually would overcome their hypocrisy.
Douglass, in terms of slavery, and to some extent racism, was right. The nation has tried to learn from its mistakes, but it has not always been successful. Douglass would not doubt be horrified by the liberties the American government has taken with freedom, after finally ensuring the rights of all. We can only hope we're still young enough to change.
Thursday, September 11, 2008
How far we've, well, mostly failed to come
We started out the week discussing Thomas Hobbes and John Locke, two terribly interesting thinkers from before and after England's Glorious revolution. I am not much of a fan of either of these thinkers; I find them much too depressing.
All due credit to Hobbes for recognizing the importance of the social contract in government, but he was a bit overzealous with his beliefs about the rights of the appointed sovereign. It's all well and good to keep one's subjects united, but there is a thick black line between a representative of the people and a despot, and Hobbes wanted the Leviathan to skip right over that line without a backward glance. There is no sense in preserving natural human rights by giving them all up to one individual or ruling body.
Locke took Hobbes ideas a step further, realizing that there must exist a means for the subject's protection against the oppression of a sovereign. Even a sovereign has to be ruled by the laws of society. Nonetheless, Locke is insistent of a higher power to rule the nation, an organization that may not be above the law, but it is certainly stuck behind it, pulling the strings of humanity's freedom.
And so John Stuart Mill enters as a breath of fresh air, taking note from the French and American revolutions and the political theorists who followed in the footsteps of Hobbes and Locke. Mill's guiding principles are the tenets of modern liberalism. I agree wholeheartedly (of course I do, I'm a liberal) with Mill's ideas.
Mill focuses on the human right to opinions and actions. He writes that for man "over himself, over his own body and mind, the individual is sovereign." Mill believes that as long as an individual takes no harmful action against another, there is no reason to prevent that individual from thinking and doing as it pleases: "the only purpose for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civilized community, against his will, is to prevent harm for others." Mill does make the exception that these principles apply only to "human beings in the maturity of their faculties," providing for the protection of children.
Mill also presents the argument that humans are civically bound to interfere when the life of another is at risk, saying "a person may cause evil to others not only by his actions but by his inaction and in either case he is justly accountable to them for the injury." This principle would be difficult to apply in a judicial setting, except in such cases as child negligence, but is certainly a belief which many people share.
Mill then takes things even a step further saying first that human liberty expands to "liberty of conscience, in the most comprehensive sense; liberty of thought and feeling; absolute freedom of opinion and sentiment on all subjects, practical or speculative, scientific, moral, or theological." This ambitious statement is certainly representative of the ideals set down in the First Amendment of the United States Constitution. Mill continues in this vein with the belief that individuals should be able to "[frame] the plan of our life to suit our own character, of doing as we like, subject to such consequences as may follow." his statement is the foundation of liberal belief in freedom of lifestyle. The ultimate dimension of Mill's theory follows that of the First Amendment's right to assembly: "freedom to unite, for any purpose not involving harm to others."
Certainly Mill's beliefs, like most liberals, are idealism of a most extreme nature. These values, while revered, are still subject to the hypocrisy inherent to all human opinions and activities.